In a previous post “What is a Semicovering Map?,” I gave an introduction to semicovering maps. A semicovering is a slight generalization of covering map that becomes particularly relevant when you’re dealing with locally complicated spaces. In particular, a semicovering is a local homeomrphism with unique lifting of all paths (for every path
and point
with
, there is a unique lift
with
). For context, I recommend taking a look at the introductory post (or the original papers [1] and [3]) first to gain intuition for the subtle difference between covering maps and semicovering maps.
A natural question to ask is: how much can we weaken the definition of “semicovering map?” More precisely, is there a weaker condition that allows us to promote a local homeomorphism to a semicovering? I really enjoy the logical investigations that these kinds of questions lead to.
This question comes from the paper [4], which gives an answer similar to the one I’ll give in this post. My interest in this question was piqued by questions of some non-Archimedian geometers, who identified a geometric analogue of semicoverings. I shared some of my suspicions with these geometers and this post is just me writing down the details. Certainly, the authors of [4] deserve the credit for originally answering this question.
Definition: We say a map has the endpoint-lifting property whenever
is a path and
is a map satisfying
,
extends (not necessarily uniquely) to a path
such that
.
The endpoint-lifting property should be thought of as a completeness-type property of relative to
: if you have a map
and it agrees with the start of a true path in
, then you can complete it to a true path
. There are some conditions on
(without referring to
) that imply this, but these include very strong compactness conditions and do not improve known results.
Example: Let be the closed topologist sine curve and let
be the projection onto the x-axis. This map does not have the endpoint-lifting property because we can define continuous map
by
. Now
,
is a path and agrees with
on
. However, we cannot assign a value to
so that
is continuous at
. You can have both spaces path conecnted if you take the projection of the Warsaw circle onto the ordinary circle.
Throughout this post, we’ll assume the space is non-empty and path connected. With this assumption, a map
with the endpoint lifting property (or stronger property) will always be surjective.
Theorem: Suppose convergent sequences in have unique limits and
is a local homeomorphism. Then the following are equivalent:
is a semicovering map,
is a Hurewicz fibration,
has the endpoint-lifting property.
Note: the condition that convergent sequences in have unique limits is formally weaker than being Hausdorff. Sometimes a space with this property is called a “US-space.”
Proof of Theorem. The proof of 1. 2. is Theorem 7.5 in [2]. I’d like to focus on the equivalence of 1. and 3 because this part is, in my view, a little more fun. By definition, a semicovering has “unique lifts of all paths rel. basepoint.” Clearly, this implies the endpoint-lifting property. The direction 1.
3. follows. The rest of this post will be to prove 3.
1.
Suppose is a local homeomorphism with the endpoint-lifting property. We must show that
has unique lifting of all paths. Let
be a path starting at
and
. We must find a unique path
such that
and
. We proceed similar to how you might prove that closed intervals are compact, that is, by defining a convenient set and analyzing the supremum. Let $$A=\{t\in (0,1]\mid \exists \beta_t:[0,t]\to E\text{ s.t. }\beta_t(0)=e\text{ and }p\circ\beta_t=\alpha|_{[0,t]}\}$$
Existence of path lifts: To show that lifts exist, we must show that . Since
is a local homeomorphism, we can find an open neighborhood
of
that
maps homeomorphically onto the neighborhood
of
. Find
such that
. The formula
gives a lift
latex of
. Therefore
and we have
. Moreover, the definition of
also ensures that
is an interval of the form
or latex
for
. Now the assumption that
has the endpoint-lifting property tells us that if if we knew
could be lifted, then we can also lift
. Hence,
must actually be a closed interval of the form
where
.
But if , we can only lift
to a path
and no more. But
is still a local homeomorphism. So we can find an open neighborhood
that
maps homeomorphically onto the open set
. Since
, we can find
such that
. Like before we define
when
. This extends
to a map
that is a lift of
.
However ; a contradiction. Since
and
is false, we must have
. This proves existence.
Uniqueness of path-lifts: To prove uniqueness, suppose both satisfy
and
. Let
Using the neighborhood of
(as above) that is mapped homeomorphically to
, we can see that we must have
for at least some small
. Hence,
. Just like
, the set
must be an interval containing
. What if
for some
? Then
but
. Picking a convergent increasing sequence
in
, we see that
and
are equal but converge to distinct limits points
and
.
However, we have assumed that convergent sequences in have unique limits. Therefore,
must be a closed interval.
Now we must show . Suppose that
. Then
. Take a neighborhood
that maps homeomorphically on the neighborhood
of
. Because
is injective,
and
lie in
for some
, and
for all
, we must have
. Thus
; a contradiction that
is the maximum. We conclude that
, i.e.
.
References:
[1] J. Brazas, Semicoverings: a generalization of covering space theory. Homology Homotopy Appl. 14, (2012) 33–63. Open Access.
[2] J. Brazas, A. Mitra, On maps with continuous path lifting. Preprint. 2020. https://arxiv.org/abs/2006.03667
[3] H. Fischer, A. Zastrow, A core-free semicovering of the Hawaiian Earring. Topology Appl. 160, (2013) 1957–1967. Open Access.
[4] M. Kowkabi, B. Mashayekhy, H. Torabi, When is a local homeomorphism a semicovering map? Acta Mathematica Vietnamica, 42, (2017) 653-663. https://arxiv.org/abs/1602.07260