The topic of this post focuses on a general concept that is heavily used in the wild topology world. Writing this post has been a fun exploration I’ve been meaning to spend time on for a while now. I will assume that all spaces involved are Hausdorff.
Definition 1: A path is (homotopically) reduced if either
is constant or if there is no interval
such that
is a null-homotopic loop, i.e. if
has no null-homotopic subloops.
I’ll usually just refer to a homotopically reduced path as a reduced path.
There are some other, more geometric, notions of “homotopically reduced” that are good for other purposes but this one is particularly relevant for one-dimensional spaces. Soon, we’ll combine new stuff with an old post to see that every path in a one-dimensional Hausdorff space is path-homotopic to a unique reduced path (unique up to reparameterization). Just as the uniqueness of reduced words in free groups is central to their theory and applications, the same kind of uniqueness for homotopy classes is important for proving things about fundamental groups of one-dimensional spaces.
History: The idea behind reduced paths in the one-dimensional case is based off of Curtis and Fort’s work in [2] from the 1950’s. I should note that Curtis-Fort use the notion of a “normal loop” which permits constant subpaths and is not exactly the same as in Definition 1. The modern definition of “reduced path,” which is far more effective for applications, does not permit constant subpaths. This modern version appears to appear first in Section 2 of Eda’s 2002 paper [3]. There is also a nice proof in Cannon and Conner’s outstanding 2006 paper [1].
Fun question to ponder: What do you think a homotopically reduced map should be for
?
Let’s start with some basic observations.
- A homotopically reduced path
that is not a constant path must be nowhere constant, i.e. there is no open set
on which
is constant. For then we could find
such that
is the constant loop, which is null-homotopic.
- In general, it’s possible for a path-homotopy class to be represented by many different reduced paths. For instance let
be the cylinder and for
, consider the paths
and
. Now the family of paths
,
are all reduced paths that represent the same path-homotopy class. See the gif below.
It’s worth pointing out that the cylinder
is a 2-dimensional space (with whatever notion of topological dimension is your favorite).
- If
is the Griffiths twin cone with basepoint
, then every non-trivial homotopy class
has no reduced representative. This is true since every loop
satisfying
is null-homotopic in
. You can start with any loop and begin pinching off null-homotopic subloops and you’ll never stop or arrive at a reduced loop. In fact it’s worse than that. No loop based at
except for the constant loop will be reduced. Interestingly, only some elements of the fundamental group of the harmonic archipelago fail to have reduced representatives. Can you find one?
What I’d like to do in this post is discuss the existence of reduced paths in homotopy classes. When can we be sure that a path is path-homotopic to some reduced path?
Say we start with a non-constant path . We want to “pinch off” or delete subloops which are null-homotopic loops. If you want to pinch things off one-by-one you’ll end up in an infinite deletion procedure, which could get pretty messy. So I think we should try to delete infinitely many subloops at a time. For example, if you have an infinite concatenation
of inverse pairs you can delete the inverse pairs one-by-one or you could just delete them all at the same time. One difficulty we could face is that if
is an infinite concatenation of null-homotopic loops, this product itself might not be null-homotopic. This phenomenon occurs precisely when the space in question fails to be homotopically Hausdorff, a concept very relevant to this post.
A Lemma about deleting constant subloops
Lemma 2: For every path , there exists a non-decreasing continuous function
and a nowhere constant path
such that
.
Proof. Let be the set of
such that
is locally constant at
, i.e. there is an open neighborhood of
on which
is constant. Let
be the connected components of
and notice that if
, then
and
must have disjoint closures. We give
the natural linear ordering inherited from
. For each
, pick a rational number
. We define
as follows:
- for each
, we set
.
- if
in
are consecutive (no element of
is between them) then for
, we use the linear function
. Doing so adds the line segment connecting
and
to the graph of
.
- If we haven’t defined
yet, then
is the limit point of a monotone sequence of intervals
in
, in the sense that
. Therefore, we define
.
A little real analysis will finish the proof that is a well-defined, continuous, non-decreasing function. As a specific example, if
is the complement of the middle-third Cantor set, and we choose the
to be the dyadic rational that is the midpoint of
. In this case,
will be a modified version of the Cantor function.
In general, is always a kind of step function like the Cantor function that is constant on the components of
.
Let’s finish this argument. Since is constant precisely on the components of
. Since
is a quotient map, and
is constant on the fibers of
, there exists a unique map
such that
.
How do we know is nowhere constant? Suppose otherwise that there exists
such that
. Since
is non-decreasing, continuous, and onto there exists
such that
,
, and
. Now
and so we must have
. By the definition of
, this means that
is a single point in
, which contradicts
. Thus
cannot be constant on any open subset of
.
Here’s why that lemma is a useful and necessary starting place: Since , we have that
and
are path-homotopic by the homotopy
. So, if we’re given a path
, we can go ahead and delete a maximal family of constant subloops in one single step without changing the path-homotopy class. Hence, toward our goal for this post, we may assume from the start that
is nowhere constant.
But….to proceed we should dissect the proof to formalize the idea of “pinching off subloops.”
Definition 3: The function doesn’t need
to be constructed. In fact, given any open set
in
and the choice of a point in each connected component of
, we can construct the function
. We’ll refer to such a function as a collapse function for
.
Notice that if is a collapse function for
and
, then
.
Lemma 4 (Pinch-off Lemma): Suppose is a path and
is a closed set such that for each connected component
,
is a loop, that is,
maps the two points of
to a single point. If
is a collapse function for
, then there exists path
such that
.
Proof. Suppose for
. Define an intermediate path
so that
In other words, is the same as
except that you force it to be constant on each component
of
.
Because is continuous,
is continuous. Moreover,
is now constant on each component of
. Since
is a quotient map and
is constant on the fibers of
, there exists a unique path
such that
. Thus
Now this new pinch-off lemma is, in a way, much stronger than our first lemma. But we must be responsible with all this power. It just says that we can always pinch of subloops to obtain some continuous path. It doesn’t say that the result will be homotopic to the original….The resulting path will be “obviously” path-homotopic to the original only if we’re pinching off just finitely many null-homotopic subloops.
Maximal Cancellations
Definition 5: A cancellation of a path is a collection
of disjoint, connected open sets in
such that for each
, the subpath
is a null-homotopic loop.
Let be the set of all cancellations of
. Notice that
has a natural partial order: given
, we say
if for every
, there exists a
such that
.
Definition 6: A cancellation is maximal if it is a maximal element of the partially ordered set
.
Observation 7: If is a maximal cancellation of
, then the elements of
have disjoint closures. For if we have
, then
would be the concatenation of two null-homotopic loops and would therefore be null-homotopic. This would mean we could define
by replacing
and
with
. This would give
, violating the maximality of
.
So, we want to know two things:
- When does a path
admit a maximal cancellation?
- If
does admit a maximal cancellation
, and we form
using a collapsing function
for
, must
be path-homotopic to
?
We’ll work to answer these questions in Part II.
References:
[1] J.W. Cannon, G.R. Conner, On the fundamental groups of one-dimensional spaces, Topology Appl. 153 (2006) 2648–2672.
[2] M.L. Curtis, M.K. Fort, Jr., The fundamental group of one-dimensional spaces, Proc. Amer. Math. Soc. 10 (1959) 140–148.
[3] K. Eda, The fundamental groups of one-dimensional spaces and spatial homomorphisms, Topology Appl. 123 (2002) no. 3, 479-505.
Pingback: Homotopically Reduced Paths (Part II) | Wild Topology
Pingback: Homotopically Reduced Paths (Part III) | Wild Topology