Infinite Commutativity (Part II)

In Infinite Commutativity: Part I, I described infinite commutativity in general terms with some basic examples, including real infinite series. In this post, I’ll discuss how the homotopy groups \pi_n(X,x_0), n\geq 2 are more than just abelian in the ordinary sense. Their infinite product operations behave like absolutely convergent series of real numbers in the sense that they are invariant under infinite permutation. I’m not going to put you through the technical proofs of the most general results. I just really love it so I’m going to try and make it as accessible and understandable as possible. The natural infinitary operations turn out to be commutative in a very strong, infinite sense. The approach I like also highlights the existence of a natural extension of the little n-cubes operad C_n(1),C_n(2),C_n(3),... to a space C_n(\aleph_0) consisting of configurations of infinitely many disjoint n-cubes.

History and Recent Work

The idea that higher homotopy groups are infinitely commutative is only 20 years old (due to Eda-Kawamura) because the proof is fairly intricate and it could easily seem overwhelming if you don’t already know how it goes. You can find it implicitly built into the main proof in [3] but even though I understand the fundamental ideas of the proof, beware that the details there are difficult to read. This idea was also used by Kawamura in [4] to study the higher dimensional earrings (sometimes called Barratt-Milnor Spheres) Following [3] and [4], infinite commutativity in \pi_n has become something of “folklore” among experts.

In the effort to formalize the infinite product framework for pushing the homotopy theory of locally complicated spaces, I’ve worked both on infinite commutativity in fundamental groups with a former student [2] and also higher homotopy groups in [1]. Part of my recent work in [1] and [2] is to make this business all more practical for computations and future applications. So I’ve been trying to formalize, simplify, and strengthen the set of available tools. This kind of math is really fun (in my opinion) and has potential to open up a lot of new avenues for research. The truth is that, right now, there are many fundamental and important open questions related to wild higher homotopy groups that are likely to become more accessible with the development of new tools/foundations, so lately I’ve been thinking a lot about these ideas.

Infinite Products in Higher Homotopy Groups

Let’s start with ordinary infinite products indexed by the natural numbers at the n-th loop space level. Since we’re talking about higher homotopy, n will always be an integer \geq 2.

For a based space (X,x_0), let \Omega^n(X,x_0) denote the space of relative maps (I^n,\partial I^n)\to (X,x_0) with the compact open topology. I’ll refer to the elements of \Omega^n(X,x_0) as n-loops. In Part I, I defined the usual binary concatenation operation \Omega^n(X,x_0)\times \Omega^n(X,x_0)\to \Omega^n(X,x_0), (\alpha,\beta)\mapsto \alpha\cdot\beta. Let’s see if we can build up infinitary operations on n-loops. Since the domain I^n.

Definition: Let K be a countable indexing set. A collection of maps \{f_k\mid k\in K\}\subseteq\Omega^{n}(X,x_0) is a null if for every neighborhood U of x_0, all but finitely many of the maps f_k have image in U.

If K is the natural numbers, then we call \{f_k\}_{k\in K} a null-sequence. Such a sequence is exactly a sequence in \Omega^{n}(X,x_0) that converges to the constant map at x_0. Let Null_n(X,x_0) be the space of null-sequences in \Omega^n(X,x_0) topologized as a subspace of the infinite direct product \prod_{k\in \mathbb{N}}\Omega^n(X,x_0).

Let’s start with the obvious first choice: given a null-sequence of maps f_k:(I^n,\partial I^n)\to (X,x_0), we may for the infinite concatenation \prod_{k=1}^{\infty}f_k=f_1\cdot f_2\cdot f_3\cdots, which is defined as f_k on \left[1-\frac{1}{2^{k-1}},1-\frac{1}{2^{k}}\right]\times I^{n-1} and f_{\infty}(\{1\}\times I^{n-1})=x_0. This is continuous at the points of \{1\}\times I^{n-1} precisely because f_k is a null-sequence.

Infinite product of 2-loops

By taking the homotopy class of \prod_{k=1}^{\infty}f_k, we get an operation \{f_k\}_{k=1}^{\infty}\mapsto\left[\prod_{k=1}^{\infty}f_k\right]. This operation is technically a function Null_n(X,x_0)\to \pi_n(X,x_0).

Warning/Red Alert!! We may want to jump quickly to writing down a partially-defined infinite sum operation of homotopy classes by setting \sum_{k=1}^{\infty}[f_k]=\left[\prod_{k=1}^{\infty}f_k\right]. The operation \{[f_k]\}_{k=1}^{\infty}\mapsto\left[\prod_{k=1}^{\infty}f_k\right] is “partially-defined” because the concatenation is continuous if and only if \{f_k\}_{k=1}^{\infty} is a null-sequence. Moreover, such an operation would only be well defined on homotopy classes if homotopic factors result in homotopic products, i.e. \prod_{k=1}^{\infty}f_k\simeq\prod_{k=1}^{\infty}g_k whenever f_k\simeq g_k for all k. This happens a lot of the time, but not always. Higher-dimensional analogues of the harmonic archipelago are counterexamples.

Here’s how infinite commutativity works for these particular kinds of infinite products:

Lemma: If \{f_k\}_{k=1}^{\infty} is a null-sequence of n-loops and \phi:\mathbb{N}\to\mathbb{N} is any bijection, then \prod_{k=1}^{\infty}f_k=f_1\cdot f_2\cdot f_3\cdots and \prod_{k=1}^{\infty}f_{\phi(k)}=f_{\phi(1)}\cdot f_{\phi(2)}\cdot f_{\phi(3)}\cdots are homotopic by a homotopy with image in \bigcup_{k=1}^{\infty}Im(f_k).

Idea of the Proof. Let’s not do a technical proof here. Instead, let’s just see how this is done in pictures in dimension n=2 with an example. Suppose \{f_k\}_{k=1}^{\infty} is a null sequence and that \phi is a specific bijection where \phi(1)=3, \phi(2)=5, \phi(3)=1, \phi(4)=2, \phi(5)=4, and so on….. To prove the lemma in this case, we’ll need to show that

\prod_{k=1}^{\infty}f_k=f_1\cdot f_2\cdot f_3\cdot f_4\cdot f_5\cdots

is homotopic to

\prod_{k=1}^{\infty}f_{\phi(k)}=f_{3}\cdot f_{5}\cdot f_{1}\cdot f_2\cdot f_4\cdots.

Our pictures will look a lot like the Eckmann-Hilton gif from Part I but with infinitely many rectangles sliding around instead of just two. I’m afraid that I wasn’t ambitious enough to animate this so all you’ll get is a sequence of still images.

Throughout the following sequence of steps, the blue squares will represent the domain of the maps f_1,f_2,f_3,... with the appropriate affine correction to the domain. If we start with the infinite product f_1\cdot f_2\cdot f_3\cdots where the domains are rectangles, of height 1, we may shrinking these rectangles within themselves to squares of side-length \frac{1}{2^k} so that the horizontal projects of the squares have disjoint interiors.

Now that we’ve done a vertical “reparameterization” we want to switch to a horizontal slide/stretch. This is where \phi comes into play. Since \phi(1)=3, we want to move the new square domain for f_3 horizontally to where f_1 used to be. As we move it, we should stretch it to width 1/2. Similarly, since \phi(2)=5, we should move the square domain for f_5 horizontally to where f_2 use to be. As we move it, we should stretch it to width 1/4. Do this for all k already! Since we had initially adjusted the heights of the domains to be disjoint we can accomplish this in one infinite simultaneous shifting process.

Now that we’ve taken care of things horizontally, it’s now a matter of some more vertical stretching to ensure that what we end up with is precisely an infinite product.

Finally, we end up with f_3\cdot f_5\cdot f_1\cdot f_2\cdot f_4\cdots where the k-th factor is f_{\phi(k)} because of our careful horizontal shifting in the middle step. Putting this all together gives a continuous homotopy H:[0,1]^3\to X. Let’s see if we can visualize the entire homotopy all at once…Remember the second animation from Part I (see figure on the left)?

Brazas

Eckmann Hilton Homotopy

Now imagine the same animation in this situation. There will be infinitely many cylinders S_1,S_2,S_3,...\subseteq [0,1]^3 with rectangle cross-sections twisting around each other in just the right way! This visualization now might have you worried that shifting around infinitely many rectangles is going to make this thing discontinuous (a valid concern!) but remember that the domain of the homotopy here is the cube [0,1]^3. The homotopy H is definitely continuous when restricted to each twisted cylinder S_k because its restriction to each cross-section is just f_k. Also, H maps [0,1]^3\backslash \bigcup_{k=1}^{\infty}int(S_k) to the basepoint x_0. So the only “hard” case is checking continuity of H at a boundary point a\in \partial S_{m} of some twisted cylinder S_m. But H maps a to x_0 and if U is a neighborhood of x_0, then Im(f_k)\subseteq U for all but finitely many k (since f_k is a null-sequence). This means S_k\subseteq f^{-1}(U) for all but finitely many cylinders S_k. Combined with the earlier observations about where H already restricts to a continuous map, it’s possible to find an open neighborhood V of a with f(V)\subseteq U (filling in the details is a good exercise for those newer to topology). This means H is continuous. \square.

Hooray! We conclude that homotopy classes of infinite products in higher homotopy groups don’t change if you start shuffling around factors. So when infinite sums are well defined and the notation \sum_{k=1}^{\infty}[f_k] for null-sequences makes sense, these sums behave very much like absolutely convergent series \sum_{k=1}^{\infty}a_k of real numbers in \mathbb{R}! But not all real infinite series are absolutely convergent. In this sense, infinite sums in wild homotopy groups are a fair bit nicer than infinite sums of real numbers. If you want to get a little fancier with your terminology, another way to phrase the above lemma is: homotopy classes of infinite products are invariant under the natural action of the infinite symmetric group \Sigma_{\infty} on Null_n(X,x_0)!

Now you can imagine how this type of argument might be generalized and altered.

Definition: An n-domain is a (possibly infinite) collection \mathscr{R} of n-cubes (subsets of the form \prod_{m=1}^{n}[a_m,b_m]) in the unit n-cube [0,1]^n with pairwise-disjoint interiors, i.e. int(R)\cap int(S)=\emptyset if R\neq S.

The next step is to generalize the idea of infinite product to make sense for a general n-domain.

Definition: If \mathscr{R}=\{R_k\mid k\in K\} is an n-domain and \{f_k\}_{k\in K} is a K-sequence of n-loops, which is null if K is infinite, then the \mathscr{R}-product of this sequence is the map \prod_{R_k\in\mathscr{R}}f_k defined as f_k on R_k and which maps [0,1]^n\backslash \bigcup_{k\in K}int(R_k) to x_0.

Be warned that n-domains are arbitrary.

Some examples of 2-domains. Each rectangular region with a blue boundary is an element of the intended n-domain.

So the main question now is….

Question: Given any two n-domains \mathscr{R}=\{R_k\mid k\in K\} and \mathscr{S}=\{S_k\mid k\in K\} and a null K-sequence \{f_k\}_{k\in K} are the products \prod_{\mathscr{R}}f_k and \prod_{\mathscr{S}}f_k always homotopic?

I can’t help but spoiling it… The answer is YES! This is a Theorem in [1]. Here’s why you should be even more startled that the answer is YES…The approach we took (in the lemma) for simultaneously sliding around individual squares/cubes fails miserably in general. It fails when you run into an n-domain that look like this:

Yikes! There’s no way to make individual moves and hope to shuffle them (after some choice of ordering) back into the simple n-domain for infinite products. If you try to move individual squares (all at once or even finitely many at a time), you will end up breaking continuity. Remember our original n-domain for defining ordinary infinite products (on the right)? How do you continuously shuffle the squares in the complicated one above to align with these ones, all of which have height 1? Aren’t we turning arbitrarily small things into big things???

It seems like there’s just too much in the way and like sequences of squares that converge to the boundary are going to be a problem. Despite all this potential concern, there is a way to do it. Once you realize the main tricks, you have a ton of freedom to move things around in the domain while still holding a continuous homotopy in your hand at the end of the day. When I was writing the paper [1], I worked really hard to find the simplest geometric procedure I could possibly imagine to get the job done. The whole time, I was imagining these infinite swarms of rectangular cylinders twisting around each other in time just like the above gif with two cylinders. I had a lot of fun working it out and I am excited to see how this formalized interpretation of “infinite commutativity” will be applied.

So… not only are higher homotopy groups commutative for infinite products, they are commutative in this super-duper-geometric-infinite way.

A comment for operad fans

One cool thing here is the extension of the little n-cubes operad. The k-th space of the little n-cubes operad is the space C_n(k) of ordered collections of k-many n-dimensional cubes (not geometric cubes but products of closed intervals) in [0,1]^n with disjoint interiors. There are a few standard ways to topologize this kind of space. I recommend Peter May’s book The Geometry of Iterated Loop Spaces.

For us infinitary-minded folks, we can take C_n(\aleph_0) be the space of all enumerated infinite n-domains, that is, all infinite collections of n-cubes in [0,1]^n with disjoint interiors. Our YES answer to infinite commutativity proves exactly that C_n(\aleph_0) is always path connected. It’s less clear if C_n(\aleph_0) is always (n-2)-connected like its finite counterparts but this seems pretty likely to me and could be an interesting future project.

Just as C_n(k) acts on the k-fold product \Omega^n(X,x_0)^k, the space C_n(\aleph_0) acts on Null_n(X,x_0)! Also, if you think about the structure maps of the little n-cubes operad, you can throw in obvious structure maps for C_n(\aleph_0) to extend it to something we could call an “infinitary operad.” Fun stuff that is ripe for exploration!

References:

[1] J. Brazas, The infinitary n-cube shuffle. Topology Appl. 287 (2020) 107446. arXiv:2006.08738

[2] J. Brazas, P. Gillespie, Infinitary commutativity and abelianization in fundamental groups. (2020). To appear in the Journal of the Australian Math. Society.

[3] K. Eda, K. Kawamura, Homotopy and Homology Groups of the n-dimensional Hawaiian earring, Fund. Math. 165 (2000) 17-28.

[4] K. Kawamura, Low dimensional homotopy groups of suspensions of the Hawaiian earring, Colloq. Math. 96 (2003) no. 1 27-39.

This entry was posted in Algebraic Topology, Higher Homotopy groups, Homotopy theory, Infinite Group Theory, Infinite products. Bookmark the permalink.

3 Responses to Infinite Commutativity (Part II)

  1. Pingback: Infinite Commutativity: Part I | Wild Topology

  2. Paul Fabel says:

    Very nice post! I am having some trouble decoding some of the technical parts, and I wonder if you could set me straight if I’m fundamentally confused. Is the story essentially the following, at least in dimension 2?

    The starting data is a null sequence of maps f_n of the unit disk, all of which map the boundary to the same point x.

    The goal is to use the starting data to construct a single global map of the big unit disk E, and hope that any two reasonable constructions yield homotopic maps.

    One way to do this is to start with a sequence of closed disks with disjoint interiors in E. Now use the map f_n to tell disk_n where to go. This is continuous, assumng the target space has reasonable properties. (Maybe it’s continuous even if the target does not have reasonable properties), this is more or less the pasting Lemma. Of course we map the complement of our disks to the special point.

    So the hope is that any two maps of E build in this manner are homotopic? So is this story more or less the whole story? It is easy to be fooled in dimension 2. Does this story work the same way in all dimensions? (Actually maybe dimension 2 is more difficult, since it’s easier for the orbits of two of the small disks to collide under the purported homotopy). Thankyou for taking the time to read this.

    Like

  3. Yes, for this post, that is the whole story. You have a null-sequence of based maps f_k:S^n\to X which, to compose, we view of as relative maps on [0,1]^n. Now take any sequence R_1,R_2,R_3,…of n-cubes with disjoint interiors in [0,1]^n. From this you can define a new map on f:S^n\to X which will be defined as f_k on R_k and maps everything else to the basepoint x. Like you mentioned, this is continuous no matter what the n-cubes look like because if U is any nbhd of x, then f^{-1}(U) will contain all but finitely many R_k (f_k was a null-sequence at x). The kicker is that if S_1,S_2,S_3,…is ANY other sequence of n-cubes with disjoint interiors (maybe some rearrangement of {R_k} or something completely unrelated like the complement of the Sierpinski carpet) and we define g to be f_k on S_k, then f and g will be homotopic! It works in all dimensions with exactly the same argument. Using sequences is just a convention I used to match up the factors f_k with which cube they should go with. The argument may seem a bit technical but it actually makes a lot of geometric sense once you’re willing to do some cube shrinking and start coming up with some clever cubical subdivisions. One key is not to go between arbitrary n-domains but rather to go from an arbitrary one to the standard sequence one.

    Why do we need it to work for crazy, arbitrary configurations of squares/cubes? Well that is exactly what is required to characterize pi_n of the n-dimension Hawaiian earring and similar spaces. As I see it, this kind of general framework should be crucial for future work on pi_n.

    Like

Leave a Reply

Fill in your details below or click an icon to log in:

WordPress.com Logo

You are commenting using your WordPress.com account. Log Out /  Change )

Facebook photo

You are commenting using your Facebook account. Log Out /  Change )

Connecting to %s